As most readers have probably learnt now, Tim Gowers’s “Tricki” is now accessible on the internet. In particular, my earlier article on Smoothing sums can be found there now, and consequently the older page I had will not be updated anymore with new material or corrections (but I have added a link to the other version). A look at the tricki’s markup language will explain that it’s much nicer to write and keep in shape these articles on the tricki than it was in the mixture of HTML and LaTeX I was using.
Author: Kowalski
Who remembers the Mills number?
One of the undetermined numbers in Les nombres remarquables is the Mills number (or numbers; this is not uniquely defined, as will be clear from the description below). I had somehow forgotten all about it, although I have now the memory that it was quite popular in the olden days (at least, I seem to remember that it cropped up in every other conversation back when I was reading that book 20 or more years ago), and I had not heard anything about it for about that long.
So, the Mills number is that (or any of the) amazing real number A>1 with the property that
$latex \lfloor A^{3^n}\rfloor$
is a prime number for every positive integer n.
As one can expect, the doubly-exponential growth means that it would be pointless to try to use this to produce prime numbers. And one may guess that the proof of the existence of such a number has little to do with primes, and should apply to many other sequences of positive integers.
This is indeed so, but not in a completely trivial manner. More precisely, what the proof shows is that, given an infinite subset S of integers, and a real number c>1, one can find B, depending of course on the set and on c, such that
$latex \lfloor B^{c^n}\rfloor \in S\text{ for all } n\geq 1,$
provided the set S has the property that, for some real number
$latex 0<\theta<1-\frac{1}{c}$
and all large enough x, the intersection
$latex [x,x+x^{\theta}]\cap S$
is not empty. In other words, since θ<1, there must be some element of the set in all “short” intervals (from some point on), where “short” has the usual meaning in analytic number theory: the length is a power less than 1 of the left-hand extremity.
(Note that the relation between c and θ shows that, if we know a suitable value of θ for S, then we can always find a value of c that works, always assuming θ<1.)
What about primes, then? Do primes exist in short intervals? The answer is, indeed, yes, and it has been known to be so since the work of Hoheisel in 1930, but this is by no means a triviality! Indeed, if one looks at the problem from too far away, analyzing the number of primes in such an interval with the “explicit formulas” in terms of zeros of the Riemann zeta function, then one gets the impression that one will prove
$latex \pi(x+x^{\theta})-\pi(x)\sim \frac{x^{\theta}}{\log x}$
(which is the expected answer, because of the Prime Number Theorem) only for θ>1/2, and only by knowing that
$latex \zeta(s)=0\Rightarrow \mathrm{Re}(s)>\theta$
which we know only for θ=1. This means that, from the point of view of immediate consequences of the location of zeros of the zeta function, having primes in short intervals is comparable with having a zero-free strip.
From this point of view, we see that the existence of the Mills number is quite an interesting fact. Moreover, the smaller the value of c one can take, the shorter the intervals we manage to find primes in. The value c=3 which I quoted at the beginning is possible because the current best result about primes in short intervals states that, for x large enough,
$latex [x,x+x^{7/12}]$
contains the “right number” of primes. (In fact, this allows any c>12/5). This result is due to Huxley, and hasn’t been improved since 1972; however, if one wants only the existence of a positive proportion among the right number of primes, Baker and Harman have the record value 0.534 (this was in 1996, and allows c>2.14…).
All the proofs since Hoheisel’s time depend crucially on a way to get around the Riemann Hypothesis known as “density theorems” for the zeros. This is a fairly inconvenient name, since “density” might suggest “lots and lots of zeros everywhere”, whereas the intent and purpose of density theorems is to show that, although there might be zeros off the critical line, or even close to 1 (which is were they would fight against the pole of the Riemann zeta function, which is the White Knight that tries to produce primes, glorious primes), there can not be too many. The precise argument is presented in Chapter 10 of my book with H. Iwaniec. Note that density theorems have many other applications: certain particularly subtle ones for Dirichlet characters (“log-free density theorems”), the first of which was proved by Linnik, are crucial to the known proofs of his marvelous theorem according to which, for some absolute constant C>0, the smallest prime P(q,a) congruent to a modulo q, for a coprime with q, satisfies
$latex P(q,a)\leq q^C.$
(The best result here allows you to take any C>5.5 for q large enough, due to Heath-Brown; the Generalized Riemann Hypothesis gives this for any C>2). If this remains too mundane — some people do not like primes in arithmetic progressions –, note that you need similar theorems for cusp forms to give an upper bound of the right order of magnitude for the rank of the Jacobian J0(q) of the modular curve X0(q) for q prime, a result of P. Michel and myself.
Now for the proof of the existence of the Mills number, in the generality of a set S containing elements in short intervals. I won’t give all details, but here’s a sketch:
(1) define b(1) to be the smallest element of S above the point after which all short intervals contain at least one element of S;
(2) define inductively b(n+1) to be such that
$latex b(n)^c<b(n+1)<b(n)^c+b(n)^{c\theta}$
(3) show, using the condition
$latex c(\theta-1)> 1,$
that if we define
$latex x_n=b(n)^{c^{-n}},\ y_n=(1+b(n))^{c^{-n}},$
we then have
$latex x_n<x_{n+1}<y_{n+1}<y_n,$
and deduce that the limit B of xn exists, and gives the desired general Mills number…
Snakes, triangles, 3×3 and what not
And now for some algebra, for a change… One of my teachers (not the pedantic one, in fact a fairly well known topologist) once told us that Homological Algebra should be learnt outside of any class, either alone in one’s room, or with friends (this is in keeping with Lang’s sole exercise in the corresponding chapter of some editions of his Algebra, which asks the reader to just take any book on the topic and prove every statement without looking at the proofs).
If you’ve followed this type of advice, there is a fair chance that you’ve only ever proved the Snake Lemma and its friends for categories of modules over a ring. As it turns out, this is not so restrictive, since some abstract theorems show that any abelian category can be embedded in such a simple one, but it might be argued that this is not very elegant, especially if the theorems in question are taken for granted without proof (or reference).
All this to say that T. Bühler gave a lecture today at our Algebra and Topology seminar, where he explained some of his recent paper (to appear in Expositiones Math.) giving complete detailed proofs of all standard diagrams and diagram chasing lemmas, starting from scratch (or more precisely from axioms for exact categories, which seem quite a bit more general than abelian categories). As he remarked at the end, doing it this way is actually shorter, and it is much more satisfactory.
Literary glory update
Alas, literary glory has eluded me. In fact, it seems that most voters did not consider “the large sieve” particularly odd at all, and my book ends last in the running (or last but one, it’s not clear from the announcement).
(And if you’re wondering: yes, I am undaunted, and I do have another book in plan despite this deadly blow).
Les nombres remarquables
As I was preparing the lecture I just gave for the SMO Day, I came back to a book I had loved when I was a kid but which I had not spent much time reading since, François le Lionnais’s Les nombres remarquables, written with J. Brette (this is a title which is surprisingly hard to translate; “Remarkable numbers” doesn’t seem right, because it misses the subtle highlighting Les).

In any case, this is a kind of dictionary of interesting numbers, which was published in 1983. I know there exist a few others, but this is the only one I’ve looked at, so I can’t compare it with them. However, this is definitely a very nice book. Partly this may be due to the fact that le Lionnais (should one say, the author, or the collector?) was not really a professional mathematician (despite what Wikipedia seems to claim in the English article), but a type of renaissance man interested both in sciences in general and a humanist; he was the co-founder (with R. Queneau, the man behind Zazie dans le métro) of the famous Oulipo. However, there is no cute amateurishness in his selection of numbers; of course, he doesn’t disdain curiosities like
843 973 902. The largest number obtained, in the decimal system, as a product of two numbers constructed with all digits from 1 to 9. 843 973 902=9642 x 87531.
but what he (or they) think are the “most interesting numbres” are highlighted with one to three stars, and the next item shows that they know that mathematics is not all cuteness:
898 128 000. *** 27 36 53 7 11. Order of the McLaughlin group, the tenth sporadic group.
There are even a few complex numbers, and some “non-determined finite numbers”. Among the first, I note the following property of
$latex e^{2i\pi /7}=0.999877\ldots + 0.015665\ldots i$
which I didn’t know (or had forgotten): the triples
$latex (a,b,c)=(1,e^{2i\pi /7},e^{6i\pi/7}) \text{ or } (1,e^{2i\pi/7},e^{10i\pi/7})$
are the only triples of (distinct) complex numbers with modulus one such that 0 does not belong to the convex hull of
$latex (a^n,b^n,c^n)$
for any integer n.
Among the non-determined finite numbers, there is the one defined as follows, which I suspect is probably determined now:
$latex N=(-1)^k10^k$
where k is the digit following the first sequence of seven consecutive sevens in the decimal expansion of π. (I think sufficiently many digits have been computed now to determine N).